Wednesday, June 24, 2020

Textualism's Malleability -- Picking Your Friends (6/24/20)

Yesterday, in a Zoom session with a Houston tax group, the Wednesday Tax Forum (which meets on Tuesday), George Connelly, here, discussed § 6751(b), here, which requires supervisor approval before the initial determination of IRS penalty claims.  Since the IRS frequently asserts penalties, this requirement has been a frequent topic in litigation, at least after it surfaced a few years ago.  Basically, the ground covered by § 6751(b) has shifted dramatically and the aftershocks continue to alter the understanding of the requirement, now in more nuanced ways than before.

I do not plan to discuss § 6751(b) in this blog. For those interested in more on § 6751(b), George’s article, titled I.R.C. Section 6751(b) – What You Need to Know, may be viewed and downloaded here.

I do want to address one of the issues that I raised in the Zoom session – that is how the Tax Court which, like other courts, has moved into or at least toward the textualist camp for statutory interpretation (see Jonathan H. Choi, An Empirical Study of Statutory Interpretation in Tax Law, 95 N.Y.U. Law Rev. 363 (2020), here), abandons textualism for § 6751(b) because the text is nonsense, and applies a purposivist reading to get to the result they think Congress must have intended (whether Congress actually intended the result or not).  (There’s that notion, purportedly anathema to textualists, that Congress’ intent, real or imagined, means anything.)

In my prior prior posting, Supreme Court Case on Statutory Interpretation (Federal Tax Procedure Blog 6/16/20), here, I discussed the theme of textualism in Bostock v. Clayton County, 590 U.S. ___, ___ S.Ct. ___ (6/16/20), here.

I just read a more robust discussion of Bostock’s themes of textualism.  Anita S. Krishnakumar, Three Lessons About Textualism from the Title VII Case, by Anita S. Krishnakumar (Notice & Comment 6/24/20), here.  In the article, Professor Krishnakumar (bio here) discusses three key topics / lessons from Bostock that are counter to the oft-repeated claims of textualism:

1. Textualism does not necessarily lead to a single correct reading of a statute.
2. Textualists care about practical consequences and other extratextual considerations.
3. Textualism often involves some speculation about legislative intent or purpose.

Professor Krishknakumar concludes:
In the end, the Court’s trio of textualist opinions in Bostock have much to teach us about what textualism means on the modern Court. And while textualists can certainly celebrate that all three opinions “flew a textualist flag” as Justice Alito put it, they also should take note that textual analysis did not produce a single clear-cut reading of the statute—and that all three opinions took into account extratextual considerations as well.
Which is to say that, well, textualism is malleable.  In that sense, could it be that textualism suffers the same argument against that textualists (at least some of them) assert for legislative history:  It is like "looking over a crowd and picking out your friends."  See Brett M. Kavanaugh, Book Review: Fixing Statutory Interpretation, 119 Harv. L. Rev. 2118, 2149 (2016), here (in fn. 157, citing "Exxon Mobil Corp. v. Allapattah Servs., Inc., 545 U.S. 546, 568 (2005) (quoting Patricia M. Wald, Some Observations on the Use of Legislative History in the 1981 Supreme Court Term, 68 IOWA L. REV. 195, 214 (1983), in turn borrowing Judge Leventhal's 'memorable phrase'").  Indeed, reading through Bostock, somehow, one might get the Humpty-Dumptian feeling that, with competing dictionaries and definitions, a word " means just what I choose it to mean—neither more nor less."  That is the textualist notion even when textualists reach different definitions.

No comments:

Post a Comment